Prolegomena

Preface
1) sad state of metaphysics vs. science. No sign of advancement.
2) Apology for Hume who has shown that the causal relation (A posited B necessarily follows) is not a child of reason, (i.e., knowable on the basis of conceptual analysis) but it is a "bastard of the imagination impregnated by experience."
How H. awakened K. from his "dogmatic slumber."

Preamble
1) Analytic vs. synthetic judgment:
Explicative (analysis of concepts) vs. ampliative (ex. All bodies are extended, vs. some bodies have weight).
2) A-priori vs. a-posteriori judgments:
Justifiable without reference to experience vs. need experiential justification (ex. 2+2=4 vs. Regan was president).
3) Grid:

                                Analytic                                         Synthetic

A-priori                        Yes                                                  ??

A-posteriori                  No                                                 Yes
 

4) Maths is

  1. a priori: Math judgments are a-priori because we know them to be universal and necessary, which they couldn't be if they were justified from experience.
  2. synthethic: although some principles used in maths (the whole greater than the part) are analytic, proper math judgments are synthetic because
 
5) Metaphysics is synthetic a priori, e.g., "substance is permanent."  However, some metaphysical statements are analytic , e.g., "substance is always a subject."

6) Is Metaphysics possible as a science?
NOTE: ultimately, the answer is 'no'
In the Critique the issue is treated synthetically, i.e., from considerations of the very nature of reason
In the Prolegomena the issue is treated analytically. We know two synthetic a priori disciplines:
i) pure maths
ii) pure physics
If by using a transcendental argument we find out what the only conditions which make them possible are, then we can see whether these conditions can possibly apply to metaphysics.
 
7)Intuition vs. concept.
Concept:

Intuition: First Part

1) Since geometry is synthetic, it must have recourse to intuition:
      a) exhibition of figures (ex. 180 degree and triangle)
      b) proofs by congruence
      c) possibility of indefinite extension of lines.
      d) tridimensionality of space.

Space provides both the medium and the constraint for geometrical construction. In other words, not merely the laws of logic, but the nature of spatiality (a brute given of human sensibility) determine geometry and what objects are geometrically, and not merely logically, possible.
NOTE: non-Euclidean geometry shows that geometry is not analytic, in the sense that the notion of triangle is not sufficient to generate the property that its internal angles amount to two right angles: one needs extra assumptions

2) Since geometry is a-priori, the intuition must be pure (a priori). Space is a pure intuition in the sense that spatiality provides the framework in which things are intuited. In other words, space is a form of intuition, and as such a transcendental condition for empirical intuition.
NOTE: An analogous story holds for Arithmetic and time.
 
3) Space/time as the transcendental conditions of empirical intuition.

 
Space and time are transcendentally ideal and empirically real. SO: 4) Incongruous counterparts (the gloves):
     a) Relational theory of space (Leibniz)
     b) absolutist theory of space (Newton)
     c) How K's argument, if it proves anything, works only against (a).

5) since geometry is based on space, the form of intuition, it must hold of anything which is perceived in space, i.e., it must hold of all outer appearances.
If we perceived not appearances, but things in themselves, we couldn't be sure that they must obey the laws of (Euclidean) geometry.
Problem:
K. proves too much: Gauss and non-Euclidean geometries.

6) distinction between critical (transcendental), empirical, and mystical idealism:

 
Second Part (with part of TD as in B,  Second Analogy and Refutation of Idealism from Critique)

1) The categories:

2) The Transcendental Deduction (sects. 15-17; 19-20 only).
Here deal only with the attempt to show the categories have objective validity, i.e. are the transcendental conditions for the representation of objects.
NOTES: sec. 15: sensibility presents us with a manifold of representations, a "manyness"; their combination (synthesis) due to the understanding.  It is this combination that constitutes experience (sensibility alone does not give the representation of any object).

sec 16: introduces the basic notion of transcendental unity of apperception (TUA), the "I think."

  1. it is analytically true, i.e., it is logically necessary, that it be possible for the "I think" to accompany all the representations of the subject.

  2. Note: the claim affirms the necessity of a possibility,i.e., it is not necessary that the subject be reflectively aware of all her representations, only that it be possible for her to be aware of them.
  3. the representation of a manifold as a manifold requires a single complex thought. Representing the manifold A, B, C, requires a single thought of A, B, C: just having a thought of A, a thought of B, and one of C won't do it.
  4. the representation of a single complex thought requires a single thinking subject: a set of distinct thoughts of the elements of a whole cannot be equivalent to the thought of the whole itelf (Example: different people saying "what a nice day").

  5. Note: traditional unity of consciousness (e.g. Descartes and Clarke); however, TUA is not empirical consciousness
  6. but a single thinking subject can represent a manifold as a manifold (i.e., have a single complex thought) only if it is possible for her to become aware of her identity with the subjects thinking each component representation of the manifold. For example, if the manifold contains representations A and B and the complex thought of the manifold is C, then it must be possible for the subject thinking C to be aware of her identity with the subject thinking A and with the subject thinking B.
  7. however, in the Treatise Hume has shown that inner sense does not provide a representation of the thinking subject.
  8. Hence, the subject thinking C can be aware of her identity with the subject thinking A and with the subject thinking B only by combining A and B in one single consciousness and being aware of being the subject who's doing the combining. That is, the consciousness that A and B are representations for the subject presupposes the subject's awareness of thinking them together as C.
  9. In sum, the identity of apperception of a manifold contains a synthesis of representations and is possible only through the consciousness of that synthesis.  Roughly put, we can represent manifolds (i.e., attach the "I think" to representations of manifolds) only if we consciously join together their component representations.
sec. 17: attempts to link TUA with the transcendental notion of an object. For K. an object is "that in the concept of which the manifold of a given intuition is united" (B 137).
NOTE: K. defines an object on the basis of the conditions that must be satisfied for it to be an object for the subject.
So, anything represented by means of unifying a manifold of intuition under a concept counts as an object. But TUA can only be obtained by the synthetic activity of the understanding, i.e., by uniting representations under a concept. Hence, TUA (the transcendental condition for thought) is a sufficient condition for the representation of objects (can't have the former and not the latter).

sec 19: links the activity of judgment to that of transcendental synthesis. A judgment is the assertion of a unity of representations by means of the copula "is" (example: "This is a dog").
But the unity brought about by judgment and that brought about by transcendental synthesis are one and the same.
Problem: Why should it be so?
So, the unification of the intuitive manifold under a concept, i.e., the representation of an object, is an act of judgment.

sec. 20: draws the conclusion that since judgments are subject to the categories, and the transcendental synthesis of the intuitive manifold is an act of judgment, the intuitive manifold must be subject to the categories.

3. The Analytic of Principles: Second Analogy .

Prelimaries:

 The argument tries to show that the application of the category (actually, the schema) of causality is a transcendental condition  for the experience of objective succession.
  1. All event perception requires successive perceptions of an object, otherwise one could not contrast the new state with the old one.
  2. But the successive perceptions of an object are merely a necessary, not a sufficient condition for the experience of an event (example: house/ship).
  3. The sufficient condition for experiencing an event is that the perceptions be thought of as being in an irreversible order. Only thus can one distinguish the experience of a succession from a succession of experiences.  For example, house-perceptions coneptualized as reversible (e.g. perception of roof before or after that of windows); but ship-perceptions coneptualized as irreversible.

  4. NOTE: this does not mean that the representations are perceived in that order, only that they are conceptualized in that order.  I conceive the ship as being at A before B, but I may perceive it at B (see the smoke) beofre I perceive it at A (hear the whistle).  Perceptions don't constitute experience of events without being conceptualized.
  5. The irreversibility of the order of perceptions can be conceptualized only by the application of an a-priori rule, which in this case is the category of causality (actually, the schema of causality).  The idea here is that an empirical concept would not guarantee irreversibility.
  6. Since the category (actually the schema) of causality is a precondition for the possibility of experiencing events, it is also the precondition for the existence of events as objects of possible experience.
Problem:
What kind of connection has to hold between a state B and its perceptual antecedent A, where the sequance A-B constitutes an event?
Two possibilities:
  1. The connection between A and B is law-like.
  2. The connection between A and B is totally accidental.
K. seems bound to claim (1) but if so, he's wrong. We recognize as objective some successions which are not causal and not law-like (example: man leaving home at t1 and being hit by a brick at t2).
Reply:
Nothing prevents K from accepting (2). There must be some causal condition determining the passage from A to B, but A needn't be the cause of B, nor need the link between A and B be law-like. The sequence A-B is conceived as irreversible because there must be some causes which determine the transition from A to B, e.g. a cause for the man being at such a place, and a cause for the brick falling there.  Conceiving A-B as irreversible (i.e as an event) entails the application of the category of causality, but not to A-B directly.

Does K answer Hume?
Possible reply:
H. must distinguish between a mere subjective sequence of perceptions and an objective sequence of perceptions because his theory of habit grounding his views of causality presuppose such a distinction. But, if K. is right, this distinction presupposes causality.
Problem: why must H. distinguish between subjective and objective succession?  The fact that the representations generating the mind are in an individual mind does not entail that they don't constitute an objective succession.
 

4. The Refutation of Idealism

Distinction between

The argument is about problematic idealism, and consequently it attempts to establish that some of the objects outer representations depict must be empirically real, i.e., real in the ordinary sense of the word.
  1. I am conscious of my existence in time, i.e., I have experience, i.e., am aware of the succession of representations.

  2. NOTE: the idea, here, is that even Descartes in the First Meditation would have to admit this.
  3. Since I don't perceive time itself, in order to determine the temporal relation of these representations there must be  "something permanent in perception," otherwise I could not become aware of their succession in a common time (I couldn't order them).

  4. NOTE:  this is, in effect, the point of the First Analogy
  5. I don't have any intuition of my particular empirical self (Hume's point)

  6. NOTE: the idea here is that one might claim that the self could constitute what's permanent in perception.
  7. All the representations in inner experience are fleeting (Hume's point)
  8. I can't have any intuition of the unity of apperception because the unity of apperception is not an intuition but an intellectual representation and as such not an item of inner experience.
  9. Hence, no object or representation of inner experience provides the "permanent in perception" required.
  10. Hence, the "permanent in perception" must be found in the actual dyachronic existence of represented objects of outer sense

  11. NOTE: K. is careful in pointing out that he's talking about the existence of outer things, and not merely about that of their representations.
Problems:  
 
Third Part (sections)

1) The only type of metaphysics possible as a science is that given in the Aestetics and the Analytic, i.e., a study of the transcendental conditions of experience, i.e., a Metaphysics of Experience.
NOTE: the point made in the Solution to the general question.

Now K. passes to study the fallacious part of metaphysics.

2) Distinction between

NOTE: Contrast transcendent and transcendental.

Ideas can be grouped under three labels: Psychological ideas, Cosmological ideas, Theological ideas (we do only a part of the second)

3)The cosmological ideas (the antinomies).

A)
The antinomies are an example of the sort of trouble reason falls into when passing beyond the limits of possible experience.
An antinomy is a pair of apparently contradictory propositions which follow from the same assumptions.
An antinomy is solved by:

B)
The four antinomies:
  1) The world has a beginning in time and is limited in space vs. the world is infinite in time and in extension
  2) every composite substance is made up of simples vs. every substance is made up of other substances, themselves made up of other substances, to infinity
  3) There are causes through freedom vs. there's no freedom but all is causally determined
  4) there is a necessary being in the world or as a cause of it vs. there is no necessary being

NOTE: K insists that the proofs given for the thesis and antithesis are correct, but there is much doubt about this.

The solution (we do just (1) and (3))
(1):

  1. Spatio-temporal objects exist only in experience (noumena are not in space/time)
  2. But the world as a whole, i.e. as one object, is not an object of possible experience

  3. NOTE: the idea here seems to be that the alleged "facts" of the infinitude/finitude of the world are not empirically accessible
  4. Hence, the very notion of attempting to find the spatio/temporal determinations of the world is inconsistent.
  5. So, the antinomy stems from an inconsistent notion, that of the world as a whole as an empirical object, i.e., as an object of possible experience.
  6. Hence, the two horns of the antinomy are both false.
(3):
  1. Universal causation applies to persons viewed as phenomena; freedom to persons viewed as noumena. But  I, as a noumenon, am a principle of action which acts uncaused (agent causation a la Clarke), while I, as a phenomenon, am subject to universal causation.
  2. Hence, the two horns of the antinomy are both true, but they apply to different areas

  3. NOTE: Implicit rejection of compatibilism, vs. Lk. and Hume.
    Problem: how does the noumenon affect the phenomena (i.e., actions)?