Religion and Morality

Morality has a long association with religion, and on most ethics panel there's a minister.  So, it’s natural to ask whether morality essentially depends on religion.
Some philosophers (e.g., Anscombe) have argued as follows:

  1. Contemporary morality uses the notion of moral obligation.
  2. The notion of moral obligation presupposes that of moral law.
  3. But a legalistic system of morality presupposes a law-giver.
  4. However, laws and norms of human society and individual conscience won't do because they are often wrong, absurd and idiosyncratic, as history amply shows.
  5. Hence, the only plausible law-giver left is God.
  6. So, contemporary morality entails a divine law theory of obligation in which moral laws are divine commands.

If the previous argument is correct, atheism precludes the possibility of morality; in other words, a secular morality is impossible, a conclusion sometimes drawn by theists
1. The basic meta-ethical issue of Divine Command Theory deals with

i. The relation between God's commands and morality:
 

Note that this does not exclude the fact that we may have special duties toward god because he’s our maker, he’s perfect, he owns our abode, and so on, and that consequently He may have moral grounds for asking us to behave thus and so because of our relation to him.  Of course, this also entails that God had moral duties toward us.

ii. The role of God in moral knowledge
One might hold that morality is religious in the weak sense that God is the only transmitter of morality.  On this view the dependence of morality on religion is epistemological.  True, there are atheists who seem to know that murder is wrong, but they don't fully know it; they are like non-physicists talking about atoms: they may get it right, but they are unable to justify or warrant their beliefs.
Problem: This view is hard to support.  That certain actions are known to be morally wrong seems the starting point of morality.  Presumably, one’s ground for one’s belief that murder is wrong is not worse than the one a religious person could offer or for the claim that god exists.

 

iii. The role of God in moral motivation.
One might argue that the presence of a God who will punish and reward us in the afterlife on the basis of our deeds is a necessary component of moral motivation. The issue is complicated because the question “why be moral?” is difficult to answer. 

The question is, of course, a challenge to justify one’s adherence to morality. One must show that well informed rational beings would choose to behave morally.  One can think of two types of justification:

1.      internal (validation).  This is within ethics itself: we have a good moral reason to be moral, and that's all that is required  

2.      external (vindication).  Here one is asking:  why should the moral way of life have priority over other conflicting ways of life (religious, self interested etc.)?  An external justification addresses a global issue:  why should I be moral at all?  Brief reflection shows that this can be an impossible question to answer if it requires to show that morality should have priority even from the standpoint of another, and opposed, way of life.  For example, if self-interest and morality do come into conflict, it would be unreasonable to demand that the defender of morality show that from the standpoint of self-interest we should be moral.  Or, if religion and morality conflict (think of Abraham on mount Moriah), it would be absurd to require a religious justification for why one ought to choose morality rather than religion.  Of course, one might believe, like Clarke, that morality and religion never conflict, and that when they seem to disagree one only has to look more carefully to find agreement, but that may be wishful thinking.    

Since typically morality is thought to conflict with self-interest, here’s an argument stating the problem:

       I.            One has a reason to behave morally only if doing so is in one’s self-interest

    II.            At times behaving morally conflicts with self-interest

 III.            Hence, at times one has no reason to behave morally

Criticism of (I):

·         It embodies a request for vindication.  But some philosophers, e.g., Kant, have rejected this as misguided, claiming that the answer to “Why should I be moral?” is “Because it is moral.”   Asking for another justification betrays a misunderstanding of the very nature of morality.  Morality is not prudence.

·         It’s not clear why only self-interest would provide a reason for action.  Why should other-regardedness be irrational?  What are the criteria of rationality here?

·         Maybe the evolutionary foundation for prosocial behavior and (probably) for morality provides a warranty for morality

Criticism of (II):

·         Morality is its own reward.  For example, self-sacrifice ennobles one (Aristotle), or immorality deforms one’s character (Plato), etc.  Doing wrong may provide some advantage but thwarts our nature preventing us from achieving true happiness (vs. mere contentment).

·         Behaving morally is always advantageous.  Here things are easier for theists.  For example, Paley thought that since God exists, wants us to be moral, and will punish and reward accordingly in the next (eternal!) life without fail, real self-interest and morality never diverge.  Or, one might argue, as Hume did, that behaving immorally while pretending to be moral (the obvious case in which immorality seems advantageous) is psychologically too demanding and ultimately leads to unhappiness.  Or that giving in to temptation even once makes it easier to give in again, which increases the chance of getting caught and punished.

However:

  1. At a minimum one might argue that acting out of fear has little or no moral worth.  As Kant puts it, threats extort but fail to impose moral obligation.
  2. Knowledge that  divine justice will be brought about makes some forms of self-sacrifice, e.g., laying down one’s life believing that there’s no afterlife, or going though hardship believing that no recompense will follow, impossible
  3. As a matter of fact, many atheists behave morally without any fear of punishment in the afterlife.

2. Problems with sacred texts and their teachings


3.  So, bracketing religious considerations far from threatening ethics is often a precondition for doing ethics reasonably.