Introductory remarks

1) Morality occupies a central role in our lives because we make moral choices every day, some trivial, e.g., whether to tell a white lie, some serious, e.g., what position we should take on abortion, the death penalty, suicide & euthanasia, punishment, animal rights etc.

We typically appeal to morality when dealing with a variety of issues such as:

2) A judgment like “The Earth is round” is different in nature from one like “Murder is wrong”.  For example, the latter involves a value judgment which we expect to result in an injunction, “Don’t murder”, towards which we should feel a duty.  Some terminological distinctions may be useful:

  1. Descriptive judgments involve the representation of "facts" in the world, e.g., that the inflation rate is thus and so, that a fetus is a member of the species homo sapiens, or that the Earth is round.
    NOTE: At times, answering a question about facts is a non-trivial affair (is the fetus a person?).
  2. Normative judgments involve valuing things, persons, states of affairs, that is, deciding which are good, better, worse, right, or wrong, etc.  So, “Murder is wrong” is an evaluative judgment

NOTE: Normative judgments typically result in injunctions

3) A moral judgment involves (1)-(2), and results in a moral duty that must be fulfilled.  Non-compliance

·         deserves punishment

·         may give rise to justified anger

·         is expected to produce guilt in the transgressor

 

4) The terms "ethics" and "morality" are often used interchangeably. However, it may be helpful to introduce the following distinction:

·         Morality is a set of practices and beliefs that include normative criteria. To be moral, one must strive to follow what morality prescribes.  Being moral requires training of the intellect and of the emotions.

·         Ethics, by contrast, is a theoretical discipline which studies morality.
NOTE: One needn't be moral to study morality any more than one needs to be a believer to study theology: being an ethicist does not involve being moral.

·         This course aims at teaching you ethics, namely at providing you with the intellectual tools to think about your moral views.  The result may be that you change some of your moral views or that you reinforce them by finding new justification for them.

5) Ethics can be divided into different somewhat overlapping branches, depending on the various ways to study morality:

1.      Descriptive ethics, which tries

a.       to describe the genesis of morality.  For example, is morality a useful human invention, like the wheel?  Or is it the product of evolutionary pressure, like blood clotting?  Or is it a divine gift to us?

b.      to understand, and explain the moral beliefs and practices, both general and particular, of a group (e.g., the Huaorani, the white business community, SIUE graduates, etc.)

2.      Philosophical ethics , which has two overlapping parts

a.       metaethics, which tries to analyze basic moral concepts (e.g., 'good' , 'right', 'duty', etc.), and to determine what counts as a justification for a moral theory. 

b.      normative ethics, which tries to determine which, if any, of the various moral frameworks is the correct one, what is desirable (not merely desired), and when a person can be considered responsible for some act. An interesting part of normative ethics is applied ethics, which tries to determine the morally correct solution to a host of moral problems in various areas of human endeavor and concern like medicine, business, the environment, the judicial system, etc.  The most concrete type of ethics is Casuistry, which studies the morality of individual actions; this is often very hard because situations can be very complex.

Note that the above areas overlap considerably.  For example, determining the genesis of morality has meta-ethical implications and is probably also relevant to normative ethics.  However, schematically one could say the following:

Descriptive ethics: What percentage of Americans think the death penalty is right?  Have their views changed lately?  If so, how?

Normative (prescriptive) ethics: Should Americans think that the death penalty is right?  That is, descriptive ethics tells us that they think thus and so, but should they? 

Applied ethics: What should Americans do about the death penalty?  Or even, supposing Mr. Smith is guilty and the death penalty justified, should he be executed, given his background, the nature of his crime, etc.

Meta-ethics: What does 'right' mean?  That is, what should we mean when we say that the death penalty is right?  That the death penalty has the property of being right as a tomato has that of being red?  That we strongly approve of the death penalty, so that when I say that the death penalty is right I really say “Up with the death penalty!”? What?

 

6) Some very basic considerations about addressing a moral issue.


i. How not to answer a normative ethical question:

1.      At most one learns how people do think, not how they ought to think.  For example, religious intolerance is evil, and the fact that it’s widely practiced makes it common, not less evil.

2.      Often people are unreflective, swayed by prejudice and passions

3.      In practice, we often witness a tyranny of the majority

1.      Before justifiably appealing to authority we need to evaluate its performance, i.e., know that it is, as it were, an authoritative authority. But this requires that we already know what's right/wrong. Of course, we may have reasons outside ethics to trust a certain authority. For example, we may trust the minister because she is trustworthy in religious matters. However, her theological ability need not transfer to moral matters. Historically, many (perhaps all) religions and sects have supported horrible practices on the basis of vies held authoritative theologians.  The same is true for political authority or familial authority (the great leader knows best, and father knows best). 

2.      Authorities disagree

3.      We should still know why an authority is right

·         By merely appealing to the law because morality and the law are not coextensive, as the existence of discriminatory laws shows.

 

·         In a purely subjectivist mode, otherwise moral disagreement becomes impossible.  If when Jim says “Homosexuality is wrong, for me” he merely means to report his subjective belief, and Joe says “Homosexuality is morally permissible, for me” in the same way, then Joe and Jim do not disagree at all.  That is, there is a conflict between them as Jim may prevent Joe from adopting children or marrying his partner, but their moral statements don’t contradict each other because each is simply reporting one’s belief.  In addition, Joe may agree with Jim that for Jim homosexuality is wrong, and Jim with Joe that for Joe homosexuality is permissible.  Consequently, if pure subjectivism is correct, as long as Joe and Jim report their views correctly no moral disagreement is possible because they are both right.  So, neither Jim nor Joe has a good reason to try to convince the other (each knows that the other is correct), and any discussion about who’s right and who’s wrong is pointless.  The result is that morality fails to provide a ground on which to resolve conflicts.  Hence, when one says “I believe that homosexuality is permissible” in a moral discussion he should not merely report one’s subjective belief; rather, one should be implicitly saying that others should also believe that homosexuality is permissible, otherwise one has moved the discussion to psychology or sociology

ii. What to look for in an answer to a normative ethical question: